Core First Amendment Rights are Implicated in This Supreme Court Case about True Threats
The internet is full of strong, impassioned, sometimes offensive language. In response to an activist鈥檚 post about being choked by a sheriff鈥檚 deputy, someone to Facebook, 鈥淲ow, brother they wanna hit our general. It鈥檚 time to strike back. Let鈥檚 burn this motherfucker鈥檚 house down.鈥 And someone listening to music lyrics about 鈥渟tudent bodies lying dead in the halls, a blood splattered treatise of hate.鈥
While this speech might be offensive 鈥 or even feel threatening 鈥 to some people, to others it is an expression of a political opinion, an unfiltered reaction to a recent event, or an attempt to rally support for a cause. The freedom to share provocative ideas and spark robust debate about political issues is essential to democracy, social justice, and progress. Our right to free speech generally protects such communications.
The freedom to share provocative ideas and spark robust debate about political issues is essential to democracy, social justice, and progress.
However, 鈥渢rue threats鈥 are not protected by the First Amendment. The government can prosecute someone who intentionally threatens another person with death or serious bodily harm, and whose language is reasonably perceived as threatening. But can a speaker be convicted of making a true threat solely because some people could reasonably perceive it as threatening, regardless of the speaker鈥檚 intent? That鈥檚 the question before the Supreme Court in Counterman v. Colorado.
The 老澳门开奖结果 and its coalition partners filed an amicus brief arguing that the First Amendment requires 鈥渟ubjective intent to threaten鈥 as a necessary element of a true threat. In other words, to meet the legal threshold for a 鈥渢rue threat,鈥 the speaker鈥檚 own intent must be taken into account. This would allow a jury to consider the speaker鈥檚 state of mind when the threat was made, and ensure that speakers aren鈥檛 criminally convicted for failures to predict how people might interpret their speech.
If a person could be convicted for any statement that could reasonably be perceived as threatening, regardless of whether they understood or intended the speech to be threatening, people would need to constantly monitor and tailor their speech to avoid potentially sparking fear in anyone who might foreseeably hear or read it. When people post on social media platforms, they would have to accurately predict how people with vastly different life experiences and perspectives might view their speech, or risk criminal prosecution.
The 老澳门开奖结果 and its coalition partners filed an amicus brief arguing that the First Amendment requires 鈥渟ubjective intent to threaten鈥 as a necessary element of a true threat.
Consider the Facebook poster saying 鈥淟et鈥檚 burn this motherfucker鈥檚 house down.鈥 Some might reasonably believe the poster will set fire to the target鈥檚 house. But if the poster intended only to hyperbolically express outrage over an injustice, their speech shouldn鈥檛 be labeled as an unprotected 鈥渢rue threat.鈥 Or consider a politician who says that if her opponent is elected, people might resort to 鈥.鈥 Some might reasonably interpret her language as a threat to her opponent鈥檚 life, even if she intended it only as an appeal for votes.
Charged speech, however, is not an internet-era phenomenon. In 1969, a racial justice activist spoke to a crowd of several hundred people and said, 鈥淚f we catch any of you going in any of them racist stores, we鈥檙e gonna break your damn neck.鈥 Today, an activist might tweet the same, intending only to garner solidarity. To criminally charge that person would silence them and chill those who similarly advocate for change.
Of course, even unintentionally threatening language can cause real harm. In Counterman v. Colorado, Billy Raymond Counterman sent C.W., a Colorado musician, a series of direct Facebook messages over a two-year period that made C.W. wonder if he was following her. Counterman, who is mentally ill, sent C.W. messages like 鈥淲as that you in the white Jeep?鈥 and 鈥淚鈥檇 like to talk directly to U, I feel neglected鈥 and 鈥渇ive years on FB. I miss you, only a couple physical sightings.鈥 C.W. didn鈥檛 respond and blocked Counterman multiple times. Each time Counterman would create a new account and message C.W. again, saying, for example: 鈥淵our arrogance offends existence of anyone in my position鈥 and 鈥淵our not being good for human relations. Die, don鈥檛 need you.鈥 C.W. obtained a protective order and canceled some of her performances out of fear that Counterman might attend.
C.W., like many people who have been sent frightening messages online, reasonably feared for her safety. In addition to posing safety concerns, threatening language is often misogynistic, racist, or homophobic. This kind of speech causes real emotional and psychological harm. Victims, fearful of more abuse, often self-censor, leaving online spaces that once brought community and well-being.
It is essential for the government to vigorously enforce restrictions on unlawful conduct, such as prohibitions on stalking and harassment, as well as restraining order violations. But expanding the definition of 鈥渢rue threats鈥 to cover speech that was never intended to threaten brings its own dangers. For example, movements for gender and racial justice often use heated rhetoric to rally support. If this speech is misunderstood as threatening and marked as a 鈥渢rue threat,鈥 then activists would have to choose between risking conviction every time they say something that could be misinterpreted, and self-censoring. The fight for progress will slowly find itself silenced out of fear. This expansion could also impinge the . A broader legal definition of a 鈥渢rue threat鈥 could come to encompass and stifle basic functions of journalism 鈥 from quoting people who hold offensive views, to publishing political cartoons, to pressing a reluctant source for comment.
As the 老澳门开奖结果 explains in our brief, a subjective intent to threaten requirement is necessary to protect speakers from being convicted of a felony simply because someone scrolling Twitter, with a different perspective and different background, might reasonably perceive their language as threatening. We hope the court will recognize the implications of its decision for advocates, protestors, and journalists, and preserve the right to speak without fear of conviction for unintentionally threatening speech.